Final Version - MS L75.372-373
|
MEMOIR 21
ON FIRST PREMISSES
My position on this subject comes under the general head of
sensationalism; but I contend that criticism is inapplicable to what
is not subject to control. Consequently, not sensation nor even
percepts are first premisses, but only perceptual judgments. I
subject what goes under the title of the test of inconceivability to
an elaborate examination, bringing out various useful truths. I also
examine the tests of universality and necessity, first adding certain
other characters which as much prove apriority as do those. These
tests have been taken in two senses, and there is a third more
advantageous than either.
From Draft E - MS L75.173-174
|
I here undertake to demonstrate that the only justifiable first
premisses are perceptual judgments, that is, judgments that a present
percept presents a certain appearance. Certain well known and obvious
objections are examined. Kant's "deductions" examined and his
position shown to be untenable. The test of inconceivability
discussed. It is fully admitted that what a man under given
conditions cannot help believing is not amenable to criticism, from
his standpoint, as long as those conditions subsist. But if he duly
considers the matter, he always can doubt, and indeed, cannot help
doubting, anything unsupported by evidence, and not a perceptual fact.
I examine the so-called tests of universality and necessity, having
shown that other characters are as well entitled to being regarded as
tests of apriority. The different senses in which these test have
been understood, as well as another in which they may be understood to
better advantage, are considered and estimated.
From Draft D - MS L75.253-259
|
Kant divided propositions into analytic, or explicatory, and
synthetic, or ampliative. He defined an analytic proposition as one
whose predicate was implied in its subject. This was an objectionable
definition due to Kant's total ignorance of the logic of relatives.
The distinction is generally condemned by modern writers; and what
they have in mind (almost always most confusedly) is just. The only
fault that Kant's distinction has is that it is ambiguous, owing to
his ignorance of the logic of relatives and consequently of the real
nature of mathematical proof. He had his choice of making either one
of two distinctions. Let definitions everywhere be substituted for
definita in the proposition. Then it was open to him to say that if
the proposition could be reduced to an identical one by merely
attaching aggregates to its subjects and components to its predicate
it was an analytic proposition, but otherwise was synthetic. Or he
might have said that if the proposition could be proved to be true by
logical necessity without further hypothesis it was an analytic one,
but otherwise was synthetic. These two statements Kant would have
supposed to be equivalent. But they are not so. Since his abstract
definition is ambiguous, we naturally look to his examples in order to
determine what he means. Now turning to Rosenkranz and Schubert's
edition of his works, Vol II (_Critik der reinen Vernunft_), p. 702, we
read, "Mathematische Urtheile sind ingesammt synthetisch." That
certainly indicates the former of the two meanings, which in my
opinion gives, too, the more important division. The statement,
however, is unusually extravagant, to come from Kant. Thus, the
"Urtheile" of Euclid's _Elements_ must be regarded as mathematical; and
no less than 132 of them are definitions, which are certainly
analytical. Kant maintains, too, that 7+5 = 12 is a synthetical
judgment, which he could not have done if he had been acquainted with
the logic of relatives. For if we write `G' for `next greater than',
the definition of 7 is 7 = G6 and that of 12 is 12 = G11. Now it is
part of the definition of `plus' that Gx+y = G(x+y). That is, that
G6+5 = G11 is implied in 6+5 = 11. But the definition of 6 is 6 = G5,
and that of 11 is 11 = G10; so that G5+5 = G10 is implied in 5+5 = 10,
and so on down to 0+5 = 5. But further, it is a part of the
definition of `plus' that x+Gy = G(x+y) and the definition of 5 is 5 =
G4, so the 0+G4 = G4 is implied in 0+4 = 4, and on down to 0+0 = 0.
But this last is part of the definition of `plus'. There is, in
short, no theorematic reasoning required to prove from the definitions
that 7+5 = 12. It is not even necessary to take account of the
general definition of an integer number. But Kant was quite unaware
that there was such a thing as theorematic reasoning, because he had
not studied the logic of relatives. Consequently, not being able to
account for the richness of mathematics and the mysterious or occult
character of its principal theorems by corollarial reasoning, he was
led to believe that all mathematical propositions are synthetic.
Kant, if I remember rightly, holds that no critical science is
necessary to establish the validity of analytic propositions. At any
rate that is the correct doctrine. But he announces, as the subject
of the great _Critik_ (observe that Kant spells this word, borrowed from
the English of Hobbes and Locke, with a `C'), the question "How are
synthetical judgments a priori possible?" I notice that Paulsen in
his book on Kant remarks that Kant never considered the question "How
are synthetical judgments a posteriori possible?", and says that if he
had done so he would have been forced to say that there are not
synthetical judgments a posteriori. But this is not true. Kant does
consider the question on page 8 of his first edition and answers it in
a totally different way from that described by Paulsen. True, he does
not go into it minutely, but he does go into it far enough to show
that he would have answered it in the general manner of my memoirs.
That page of the _Critik_ is a pregnant one, but it is in strictest
harmony with Kant's general position. Kant's precise question now
comes before us for answer. But he does not state it quite
accurately. It is not the question how synthetical judgments are
possible, which it is for the psychologists to explain, but how they
can be known to be true. In place of Kant's division of judgments
into the a priori and the a posteriori, I prefer to begin by dividing
them into inferential judgments and ultimate premisses. By an
ultimate premiss we must understand a judgment not derived by an
ascertainably self-controlled logical process.
As to inferred judgments, they are to be justified by the
methods of argument by which they have been derived; and the
justification of different classes of arguments will be considered in
the memoirs immediately following the present one.
As to ultimate premisses, my categories help me in a remarkable
way to show, from the nature of propositions, that every judgment so
formed must consist in judging that a present percept has a certain
kind of appearance, and that from the nature of logical critic such
judgments are not amenable to criticism.
From Draft D - MS L75.325-326
|
It is not the question of how synthetical judgments are
possible, which would be a psychological question, but how they can be
true and known to be true. I shall not make his division of judgments
into the a priori and the a posteriori the leading one, but rather the
division into derived and ultimate propositions. By an ultimate
premiss we must understand a proposition not derived by an
ascertainably self-controlled logical process.
I shall make a logical analysis of the logical, not
psychological, nature of doubt, and shall show that no doubt can
attach to an ultimate judgment; and I shall further show that such
judgments are necessarily perceptual judgments; that is, that such a
judgment simply judges that a present percept has a certain
appearance. This discussion will be very elaborate and careful. It
shows that perceptual judgments alone are not amenable to criticism.
As for derived judgments, they must always remain open to doubt;
but they are justified in the measure in which the arguments which
lead to them are justified. It will now be necessary for me to enter
into a detailed criticism of all the opinions which are opposed to my
conclusions. I shall have to consider the opinion that logical
criticism goes back to the first impressions of sense, as Kant and
many non-Kantians assume.
From Draft D - MS L75.315-324
|
It is not the question how synthetical judgments are possible,
which would be a psychological question, but how synthetical
propositions can be true and be known to be true. But I shall not
make his division of propositions into the a priori and the a
posteriori the leading one, but rather the division into derived and
ultimate propositions. We must be on our guard in defining this
distinction not to fall into a mere matter of psychology, as Kant
does, floundering in a muddy bog of land and water, a psychological
deduction and a "transcendental" deduction mixed. By an ultimate
premiss we must understand a proposition not derived by an
ascertainably self-controlled logical process. We need not assume
that there is any premiss over whose derivation it is impossible to
exercise any control. It will suffice that, in fact, as far as we
have ascertained, there has been no such control. Derived
propositions are justified by the arguments by which they are
derivable; and the justification of such arguments will be considered
in subsequent memoirs. In regard to underived propositions, we may
for the moment compare a man who makes a judgment with a piece of
paper on which a proposition is written. If somebody has idly written
on a piece of paper, `The moon is made of green cheese', he has not
made himself responsible for the truth of the proposition; and if it
were asked how the paper was justified for carrying such a lie, the
obviously sufficient answer would be it cannot help it. In like
manner if a man looks at the moon and judges that it looks bright,
this judgment is entirely unlike the percept from which it is derived,
and still more unlike the first impressions of sense. Still, we have
no need of following Kant in attempting to make out what the
psychological process is. No use could be made of such knowledge, if
we had it, and Kant's psychological deduction is manifestly idle. The
one perfectly sufficient justification is that the man can no more
help judging that the moon he is looking at seems bright than a piece
of paper can help what is written upon it. For who is to find fault
with him? As long as he keeps his opinion to himself, as long as he
cannot help believing that the moon looks bright, he does believe it
perfectly; and as long as he does believe it perfectly, he does not in
the least doubt it, and as long as he cannot help believing it, he
cannot doubt it. In short it appears to him evidently true; and he
cannot blame himself for believing what is manifestly true. He cannot
so much as make an effort to believe otherwise. "So, then," somebody
may say, "you believe in the test of inconceivability." But nobody
has any right to draw such an inference. On the contrary, it is
fairly presumable that I am consistent in my opinions; and consistency
with what I have just been saying forces me to declare, not indeed
that the test of inconceivability is untrustworthy, but that the
phrase `test of inconceivability' is a self-contradictory jumble of
words, and that nobody can either trust to it or distrust it, since
there is no such thing. If a man cannot help entirely believing that
a proposition is true, it is absurd for him to pretend that his not
being able to doubt it is his reason for believing it. He has no
reason whatever for believing it; for reasoning is essentially
self-controlled, while he cannot help believing it. A reason is only
operative while a man is changing his mind. When he is once
convinced, we say he has a reason for his belief; but that only means
that he can imagine himself to be oblivious of the reason and to doubt
the proposition and that he sees, or thinks he sees, that if that were
the case, the knowledge of the reason would silence his doubts.
Strictly speaking, he is not now under the influence of the reason;
and he "has" a reason for his belief only in the sense of having
stored in his mind something which he feels would act as a reason
should he ever be led to doubt the proposition. A man has no reason
for what he does not doubt, still less any such ridiculous reason as
that he does not doubt it. I know that it may be said that the test
of inability to doubt is one thing and the test of inability to
conceive is another. But I deny it. What those people mean who talk
of the test of inconceivability [i.e. what this] means to them [is]
simply erecting inability to doubt into a reason. It is true that
their minds are in a confused state, as their language shows. It will
be shown that true inconceivability can only arise as a consequence of
what is called self-contradiction. But many things are said by
logically untrained minds to be inconceivable because they seem to
them so strange that they do not know how to go to work to frame the
conception. For example, many persons would say that a man's being
the father of his own father was inconceivable. But there are various
ways in which such an event may be conceived, as, for example, by
simply supposing that all time forms a closed cycle which the two
lives completely exhaust. Certainly, unless there is some abstruse
reason to the contrary which does not at once strike me, it is quite
possible that, as a matter of fact, time does form a closed cycle. At
the same time, until some positive reason shall appear for believing
that it is so, it will be shown in another memoir that we are
justified in disbelieving it; and it is simply because they cannot
entertain a doubt on the subject, that some people pronounce the idea
inconceivable; unless they are dominated by the narrowest associations
of ideas.
Now what are the things which cannot be doubted? I will begin
by abandoning the field of pure logic, and asking what are the things
that I personally, find I cannot doubt. Doubt may be present in very
slight degree. Suppose there are a thousand propositions that, as far
as I can see, I do not, in fact, in the least doubt. Still, I might
think viewing them collectively, that some one of them, I know not
which, may be erroneous. I certainly do believe that among all the
opinions which I most firmly hold there are errors, very likely a good
many errors. This could not be if I had not the smallest doubt of any
one of them. There are doubts, then, in my mind which are so faint
that with all the energy of attention which I can well bestow upon the
scrutiny of my state of mind, I am not able to discern. But if there
by anything that I do not doubt at all, it must be a proposition the
evidence for which presents itself in its entirety here and now. For
although a compulsion may conform to a general law, it cannot have any
mode of being other than that of direct activity here and now. It
can, therefore, be no general proposition. It must be a perceptual
judgment; that is, the judgment that a present percept has a certain
appearance.
At the same time, I cannot, by a mental operation, doubt
anything which I do not already doubt. I do not mean to deny that a
surprising experience might create doubts not previously existing. I
cannot even review the evidence for a belief, unless I entertain a
doubt of it. Moreover, every doubt which I entertain is founded upon
some reason for a contrary belief. But when, in consequence of a
slight doubt, founded, perhaps, upon no more definite reason than that
I have often found myself mistaken, I am led to reexamine the
evidence, it very frequently happens that I discover some circumstance
which creates a doubt very much stronger, and founded upon altogether
different reasons.
Passing now to the pure logical doctrine, an assertion is an act
which represents that an icon represents the object of an index.
Thus, in the assertion, `Mary is red-headed', `red-headed' is not an
icon itself, it is true, but a symbol. But its interpretant is an
icon, a sort of composite photograph of all the red-headed persons one
has seen. `Mary' in like manner, is interpreted by a sort of
composite memory of all the occasions which forced my attention upon
that girl. The putting of these together makes another index which
has a force tending to make the icon an index of Mary. This act of
force belongs to the second category, and as such, has a degree of
intensity. Not that degree in itself belongs to the second category.
On the contrary, it belongs to the third. Degree is not a reaction,
or effort, but a thought. But degree attaches to every reaction.
Consequently, every assertion has a degree of energy.
From Draft D - MS L75.259-262
|
Either at this point or later in the memoir, I shall examine the
so-called tests [of] universality and necessity which are supposed to
prove the a priori character of certain propositions. I shall first
trace the history of this doctrine. I shall then show that the
statement of it is incomplete, there being a number of other
characters which are equally entitled to be considered as tests of
apriority. I shall then show that there are two senses in which the
test has been understood; and that there is a third sense which makes
a more defensible doctrine than either. I show that the test may be
understood to embody several logical truths; yet if any proposition is
universal, necessary, etc., and there is nothing to show that it is
true, the only logical position is that it is false. A first premiss,
other than a fact of perception, is inadmissible. Kant's position is
that it is easy to show by universality and necessity that certain
propositions are a priori, but that their truth remains to be proved
by an abstruse line of reasoning. Now it would [be] absurd to admit
into that reasoning any a priori proposition as long as one maintains
that such reasoning is necessary to support any a priori proposition;
and in fact Kant's premisses appear to be quite evidently
generalizations of common experience. But granting that he in this
way proves the truth of an a priori proposition, it follows that
antecedently to this proof it was an idle hypothesis, and that its
only support is a purely experiential argument. But that is pure
positivism; and Kant's doctrine really seems to be nothing but
nominalistic sensualism so disguised that it does not recognize
itself. Of course, it may be said that Kant only maintains the
concepts, not the judgments, to be a priori. In the first place, this
is directly contrary to Kant's own opinions. In the next place,
universality and necessity are characters of propositions, not of
terms. In the third place, Hume himself, even as Kant misrepresents
him, [and] much more [i.e., and all the more] in his true character,
would have been ready to admit that some forms of thought arise from
the nature of mind. Some persons who have believed themselves to be
Kantians hold that as soon as a proposition is shown to be a priori,
it is beyond all criticism. That is utterly contrary to the spirit of
Kant. But it is quite true that if there is anything which I cannot
help believing without any tincture of doubt, I am out of all real
discussion of its truth. No doubt that for many persons there are
such propositions, if by doubt we mean any doubt that they recognize;
and if by `can', we refer to ability conditioned upon such means as
they have put into practice. Propositions so believed are almost
always false; but there is no way for their victims to be undeceived
as long as they cherish that state of mind. This seems to be the
state of all those persons who think that philosophy and logic are
idle things; that all that is required is a little good sense and
reflection, and that extensive reading and study are useless.
The previous memoir, No. 20, will have contained an elaborate
analysis of the logical nature of doubt which will be applied to the
problems of the present memoir, especially to show that judgments
founded on the experience of every hour of every man's life are not
subject to doubt of the ordinary kind and have some of the
characteristics attributed to a priori propositions.
Other views will be critically examined.
Final Version - MS L75.373-375
|
MEMOIR 22
THE LOGIC OF CHANCE
I here discuss the origin and nature of probability by my usual
method; also the connection between objective probability and doubt;
the nature of a "long run"; in what sense there can be any probability
in the mathematical world; the application of probability to the
theory of numbers. I show that it is not necessary that there should
be any definite probability that a given generic event should have a
given specific determination. It is easy to specify cases where there
would be none. There appears to be no definite probability of a
witness's telling the truth. I also show that it is quite a mistake
to suppose that, for the purposes of the doctrine of chances, it
suffices to suppose that the events in question are subject to unknown
laws. On the contrary, the calculus of probability has no sense at
all unless it in the long run secures the person who trusts to it.
Now this it will do only if there is no law, known or unknown, of a
certain description. The person who is to trust to the calculus ought
to assure himself of this, especially when events are assumed to be
independent. The doctrine of chances is easily seen to be applicable
in the course of science. Its applicability to insurance companies
and the like is not in any case to be assumed off-hand. When it comes
to the case of individual interests, there are grave difficulties.
The rules of probability are stated in a new way, with the
application of high numbers and method of least squares according to
several different theories. Pearson's developments examined. Inverse
probabilities are shown to be fallacious.
There are many matters here under dispute; more than I here set
down. In all these cases, I take pains to state opposing arguments in
all their force, and to refute them clearly.
This memoir is intended to form a complete vade mecum of the
doctrine of chances, and to be plentifully supplied with references.
It will be somewhat long, but I hope not of double length.
From Draft D - MS L75.263-268
|
Deduction, as such, is not amenable to critic; for it is
necessary reasoning, and as such renders its conclusions evident. Now
it is idle to seek any justification of what is evident. It cannot be
rendered more than evident. Fallacies, it is true, may be criticized;
but this subject will be postponed until all the legitimate modes of
argument have been considered.
But when deduction relates to probability, it becomes open to
criticism, not insofar as it is deductive but insofar as it relates to
a logical conception which in a sense deprives the reasoning of its
necessary character. I therefore in this memoir examine the nature of
probability, and the processes of the doctrine of chance. I flatter
myself that I shall put the whole matter, both of the origin of
probability and of the application of the calculus, in a much clearer
light than has hitherto been done. Objective probability is simply a
statistical ratio. But, besides that, doubt has degrees of intensity,
and although these have no necessary signification, it might be useful
for us to believe more intensely in propositions which would less
often deceive us than in such as would oftener deceive us. In point
of fact, we naturally "weigh" or "balance reasons," as if the degree
of our trust in them were significant of fact. This is a matter
requiring minute examination.
In the first place, regarding probabilities as statistical
ratios, probability is exclusively confined to cases where there is a
"long run" of experience, that is, an endless series of events of a
general character, of which some definite ratio have a special
character, which shall not occur at any regular law of intervals. It
is not necessary that this ratio should remain constant throughout the
experience. But it is requisite that there should be such a ratio.
It is easy to imagine cases in which there should be no such ratio;
perhaps even a universe in which there should be no such thing as
probability. (I will endeavor to determine this with certainty before
drawing up the memoir.) It is commonly said that there is a law of
the occurrence of the event, only it is unknown to us. But it is easy
to show that the utility of the calculus depends on there being no law
of the kind which would concern the application. Ignorance is not
sufficient.
The rules of probability are easily deduced, involving the
conception of independent events, that is, events such that the
product of the number of occurrences of both into the number of
non-occurrences of both equals the product of the number of
occurrences of the first only into the number of occurrences of the
second only. From this follows the probability law.
Now as concerns the connection between probability and doubt, we
find the books stuffed with errors. It is, for example, generally
said that probability 1 represents absolute certainty. But on the
contrary, probability 1 is that of an event which in the entire long
run fails to occur only a finite number of times. In the next place,
the majority of the books give formulae from which it would follow
that the probability of a wholly unknown event is 1/2. It is evident
that probability, in this crude form, is quite unadapted to expressing
the state of knowledge generally. The relation of real evidence to a
positive conclusion is not a mathematical function. From a bag of
beans, I take out a handful, in order to test a theory which I have
some other reason for entertaining, that two thirds of the beans in
the bag are black. I find this to be nearly so in the handful, and my
theory is confirmed, and I now have strong reason for believing it
approximately true. But it is not true that there is any definite
probability that it is true. For what would such a ratio mean? Would
it mean that once in so often my conclusion is true? That depends on
the general commonness of different distributions of beans in a bag,
which is a positive fact, not a mathematical function. Mathematical
calculation is deductive reasoning, applicable solely to hypotheses;
and whenever it is applied to do the work of induction or abduction it
is utterly fallacious. This is an important general maxim.
This consideration affects the method of least squares, if this
method is looked upon in an extravagant theoretical manner; but not if
it is regarded as a way of formulating roughly an inductive inference.
Mr. Pearson's extensions, though they are excessively complicated, and
thereby violate the very idea of least squares, are not without value.
but other somewhat similar modifications of probability are called
for; and I shall endeavor to work out one or two of them.
I give in this memoir a summary of all the ordinary scientific
man needs to know about probability in a brief intelligible manner.
It will have the advantage over Bertrand's book of being sound.
From Draft D - MS L75.311-312
|
Although deduction is not directly and as such amenable to
critic, yet it becomes such when it deals with probability and certain
allied conceptions. The criticism is not properly of the deductive
process but of those conceptions. I here examine the philosophy of
probability and show, among other things, that it is by no means true
that every contingent event has any definite probability. I describe
the construction of an urn of black and white balls such that there is
no definite probability that a ball drawn will be white. By way of
illustration, I show that there is no definite probability that a
witness will tell the truth. Another point I make clear is the
distinction between probability unity and certainty. This is
illustrated by the case where a large number of players, playing
against a banker, at a perfectly even game, each bet one franc each
time until his [bet] nets a gain, when he retires from the table and
gives place to a fresh player. The probability is 1 that any given
player will ultimately net a gain, and therefore that all will do so;
and yet the probability is 1 that in the long run the bank will not
lose, or at any rate, there is an even chance that if the banker does
not come out precisely even he will win, too. I show that the "moral
value" of a player's chances is quite irrelevant to the Petersburg
paradox; and I correct various other errors current about probability.
Hume's argument about miracles will be analyzed.
Rules by which all errors in the use of the doctrine of chances
[can be identified] will be plainly laid down, and their use
exemplified.
Final Version - MS L75.375
|
MEMOIR 23
ON THE VALIDITY OF INDUCTION
This restates the substance of the Johns Hopkins paper:
relegating formalistic matters to separate sections, taking account of
types of induction with which I was not acquainted twenty years ago,
and rendering the whole more luminous. Other views will be considered
more at large.
From Draft E - MS L75.176
|
This memoir will repeat substantially the theory of induction
given in my paper in the John Hopkins Studies in Logic, but now stated
in essential points more fully and clearly, while formalistic matters
are relegated to special sections. Moreover, my subsequent discovery
of forms of induction quite different from any there considered, to
which the applicability of the rules there developed is not evident,
renders a new presentation necessary. I shall now consider other
views more fully, and illustrate the bad influence they have had upon
science.
From Draft D - MS L75.268-270
|
It will be shown to be mathematically impossible that induction
indefinitely persisted in should ultimately lead to a false conclusion
in any case whatsoever, whether there be any definite probability or
not, whether there be any real universe or not, whether the universe
be presided over by a malign power bent upon making inductions go
wrong or not. Such things might prevent inductions from being drawn,
but they could not make them go ultimately wrong if they were rightly
conducted and sufficiently persisted in. From this principle follow
certain rules of induction for each of the three types of induction.
These rules are clearly formulated and illustrated historically.
I then proceed to inquire how far inductions may be strengthened
or weakened by other arguments, which do not in themselves afford any
information concerning the subjects of inquiry in the inductions, but
which do give information strengthening or weakening any conclusions
obtained. In particular, I show that the knowledge of certain
uniformities (of which four types are the simplest) may so affect
inductions.
I now review all the other theories of induction, beginning with
that of LaPlace which undertakes to assign a definite probability to
the inductive conclusion. I show that that is erroneous, and that,
rightly applied, Laplace's method would lead to the result that we
know nothing about the truth of the conclusion. I next examine those
theories that the future is like the past, that the universe presents
great uniformity, and demonstrate that assuming those premisses to be
true, they do not in the least help the validity of induction. I show
that all such statements really mean nothing except that a badly
conducted induction will lead to the truth, and that they are not
true. The question of whether there is any objective sense in which
they are true will be postponed to a separate memoir. I go on to
consider several other theories of induction which mostly amount to
denying its validity.
From Draft A - MS L75.39-42
|
The doctrine commonly held that the validity of induction
depends upon the uniformity of nature, or what comes to the same
thing, upon the resemblance of the future to the past, is erroneous.
I find that there are no less than eight incompatible ideas of what
the uniformity of nature consists in, which not only have been put
forward, but are widely current. But the doctrine is false in every
sense. The most usual meaning attached to whichever of the two
phrases happens to approve itself is really nothing but a dimly
apprehended notion that some one of the lower forms of induction is
valid reasoning. This will be proved incontestably in my book. Now
it is nonsense to say that the validity of induction depends upon
itself; and it is false that the validity of the highest forms depends
solely on that of any lower form. Consequently, the doctrine, as
ordinarily held, is nothing but a twist of language by which the
validity of some kind of induction is restated in other words. If any
of the other seven meanings is attached to the phrase `the uniformity
of nature', there is no difficulty in supposing a world which should
not present that uniformity. Now two of the meanings attached to the
phrase are such that in a world without uniformity no induction, good
or bad, could be drawn. In such a world, there could be no
experience, properly speaking, and no reasoning of any kind. But the
moment one supposes the universe to be such that a false induction
becomes possible, I prove by mathematical demonstration that pure
induction has all the validity that it has in the actual universe,
although it cannot, perhaps, be fortified by the discovery of special
uniformities. But an argument from a uniformity is not inductive; it
is a deduction going to fortify an induction which is made a matter of
observation.
The thought may suggest itself[,] that the question whether the
validity of induction rests on the uniformity of nature or what[,] is
a somewhat idle one, of no practical importance. But such an opinion
will be retracted by a reasonable man as soon as he learns, as my book
will prove beyond possible dispute, that from my doctrine of the
validity of induction it follows necessarily that certain rules and
precautions ought to be observed in the practice of induction, at the
peril of great mistakes, which rules and precautions are habitually
disregarded by all but the keenest and most careful reasoners. My
doctrine makes the security of induction wholly depend upon the
honesty and skill of the inquirer. The other doctrine throws off all
responsibility and puts it upon the broad shoulders of Nature. The
consequence is that these logical treatises which rest the validity of
induction upon a special constitution of nature have no reason for
insisting and in fact do not point out at all the essential
precautions which are as indispensable to the security of the
proceeding as they are usually neglected.
End of PART 7 of 10 of MS L75
|